Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Obj. 3:  Further, Cicero says (De Invent.  Rhet. ii) that “virtue is a habit like a second nature, in accord with reason.”  But since every human virtue is directed to man’s good, it must be in accord with reason:  since man’s good “consists in that which agrees with his reason,” as Dionysius states (Div.  Nom. iv).  Therefore every virtue is a moral virtue.

On the contrary, The Philosopher [says] (Ethic. i, 13):  “When we speak of a man’s morals, we do not say that he is wise or intelligent, but that he is gentle or sober.”  Accordingly, then, wisdom and understanding are not moral virtues:  and yet they are virtues, as stated above (Q. 57, A. 2).  Therefore not every virtue is a moral virtue.

I answer that, In order to answer this question clearly, we must consider the meaning of the Latin word mos; for thus we shall be able to discover what a moral virtue is.  Now mos has a twofold meaning.  For sometimes it means custom, in which sense we read (Acts 15:1):  “Except you be circumcised after the manner (morem) of Moses, you cannot be saved.”  Sometimes it means a natural or quasi-natural inclination to do some particular action, in which sense the word is applied to dumb animals.  Thus we read (2 Macc. 1:2) that “rushing violently upon the enemy, like lions [Leonum more, i.e. as lions are in the habit of doing], they slew them”:  and the word is used in the same sense in Ps. 67:7, where we read:  “Who maketh men of one manner (_moris_) to dwell in a house.”  For both these significations there is but one word in Latin; but in the Greek there is a distinct word for each, for the word _ethos_is written sometimes with a long, and sometimes a short _e._

Now moral virtue is so called from mos in the sense of a natural or quasi-natural inclination to do some particular action.  And the other meaning of mos, i.e. custom, is akin to this:  because custom becomes a second nature, and produces an inclination similar to a natural one.  But it is evident that inclination to an action belongs properly to the appetitive power, whose function it is to move all the powers to their acts, as explained above (Q. 9, A. 1).  Therefore not every virtue is a moral virtue, but only those that are in the appetitive faculty.

Reply Obj. 1:  This argument takes mos in the sense of custom.

Reply Obj. 2:  Every act of virtue can be done from choice:  but no virtue makes us choose aright, save that which is in the appetitive part of the soul:  for it has been stated above that choice is an act of the appetitive faculty (Q. 13, A. 1).  Wherefore a habit of choosing, i.e. a habit which is the principle whereby we choose, is that habit alone which perfects the appetitive faculty:  although the acts of other habits also may be a matter of choice.

Reply Obj. 3:  “Nature is the principle of movement” (Phys. ii, text. 3).  Now to move the faculties to act is the proper function of the appetitive power.  Consequently to become as a second nature by consenting to the reason, is proper to those virtues which are in the appetitive faculty. ________________________

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.