Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

(7) Whether any delight is non-natural?

(8) Whether one delight can be contrary to another?
________________________

FIRST ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 31, Art. 1]

Whether Delight Is a Passion?

Objection 1:  It would seem that delight is not a passion.  For Damascene (De Fide Orth. ii, 22) distinguishes operation from passion, and says that “operation is a movement in accord with nature, while passion is a movement contrary to nature.”  But delight is an operation, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. vii, 12; x, 5).  Therefore delight is not a passion.

Obj. 2:  Further, “To be passive is to be moved,” as stated in Phys. iii, 3.  But delight does not consist in being moved, but in having been moved; for it arises from good already gained.  Therefore delight is not a passion.

Obj. 3:  Further, delight is a kind of a perfection of the one who is delighted; since it “perfects operation,” as stated in Ethic. x, 4, 5.  But to be perfected does not consist in being passive or in being altered, as stated in Phys. vii, 3 and De Anima ii, 5.  Therefore delight is not a passion.

On the contrary, Augustine (De Civ.  Dei ix, 2; xiv, 5 seqq) reckons delight, joy, or gladness among the other passions of the soul.

I answer that, The movements of the sensitive appetite, are properly called passions, as stated above (Q. 22, A. 3).  Now every emotion arising from a sensitive apprehension, is a movement of the sensitive appetite:  and this must needs be said of delight, since, according to the Philosopher (Rhet. i, 11) “delight is a certain movement of the soul and a sensible establishing thereof all at once, in keeping with the nature of the thing.”

In order to understand this, we must observe that just as in natural things some happen to attain to their natural perfections, so does this happen in animals.  And though movement towards perfection does not occur all at once, yet the attainment of natural perfection does occur all at once.  Now there is this difference between animals and other natural things, that when these latter are established in the state becoming their nature, they do not perceive it, whereas animals do.  And from this perception there arises a certain movement of the soul in the sensitive appetite; which movement is called delight.  Accordingly by saying that delight is “a movement of the soul,” we designate its genus.  By saying that it is “an establishing in keeping with the thing’s nature,” i.e. with that which exists in the thing, we assign the cause of delight, viz. the presence of a becoming good.  By saying that this establishing is “all at once,” we mean that this establishing is to be understood not as in the process of establishment, but as in the fact of complete establishment, in the term of the movement, as it were:  for delight is not a “becoming” as Plato [Phileb. 32, 33] maintained, but a “complete fact,” as stated in _Ethic._ vii, 12.  Lastly, by saying that this establishing is “sensible,” we exclude the perfections of insensible things wherein there is no delight.  It is therefore evident that, since delight is a movement of the animal appetite arising from an apprehension of sense, it is a passion of the soul.

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.