Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 1,748 pages of information about Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae).

FIFTH ARTICLE [I-II, Q. 56, Art. 5]

Whether the Sensitive Powers of Apprehension Are the Subject of
Virtue?

Objection 1:  It would seem that it is possible for virtue to be in the interior sensitive powers of apprehension.  For the sensitive appetite can be the subject of virtue, in so far as it obeys reason.  But the interior sensitive powers of apprehension obey reason:  for the powers of imagination, of cogitation, and of memory [Cf.  I, Q. 78, A. 4] act at the command of reason.  Therefore in these powers there can be virtue.

Obj. 2:  Further, as the rational appetite, which is the will, can be hindered or helped in its act, by the sensitive appetite, so also can the intellect or reason be hindered or helped by the powers mentioned above.  As, therefore, there can be virtue in the interior powers of appetite, so also can there be virtue in the interior powers of apprehension.

Obj. 3:  Further, prudence is a virtue, of which Cicero (De Invent.  Rhetor. ii) says that memory is a part.  Therefore also in the power of memory there can be a virtue:  and in like manner, in the other interior sensitive powers of apprehension.

On the contrary, All virtues are either intellectual or moral (Ethic. ii, 1).  Now all the moral virtues are in the appetite; while the intellectual virtues are in the intellect or reason, as is clear from Ethic. vi, 1.  Therefore there is no virtue in the interior sensitive powers of apprehension.

I answer that, In the interior sensitive powers of apprehension there are some habits.  And this is made clear principally from what the Philosopher says (De Memoria ii), that “in remembering one thing after another, we become used to it; and use is a second nature.”  Now a habit of use is nothing else than a habit acquired by use, which is like unto nature.  Wherefore Tully says of virtue in his Rhetoric that “it is a habit like a second nature in accord with reason.”  Yet, in man, that which he acquires by use, in his memory and other sensitive powers of apprehension, is not a habit properly so called, but something annexed to the habits of the intellective faculty, as we have said above (Q. 50, A. 4, ad 3).

Nevertheless even if there be habits in such powers, they cannot be virtues.  For virtue is a perfect habit, by which it never happens that anything but good is done:  and so virtue must needs be in that power which consummates the good act.  But the knowledge of truth is not consummated in the sensitive powers of apprehension:  for such powers prepare the way to the intellective knowledge.  And therefore in these powers there are none of the virtues, by which we know truth:  these are rather in the intellect or reason.

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Summa Theologica, Part I-II (Pars Prima Secundae) from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.