Theodicy eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 660 pages of information about Theodicy.

Theodicy eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 660 pages of information about Theodicy.

SECOND SYLLOGISM

’The work most worthy of God’s wisdom involves amongst other things the sin of all men and the eternal damnation of the majority of men.

’Now God wills of necessity the work most worthy of his wisdom.

’He wills therefore of necessity the work that involves amongst other things the sin of all men and the eternal damnation of the majority of men.’

The major holds good, but the minor I deny.  The decrees of God are always free, even though God be always prompted thereto by reasons which lie in the intention towards good:  for to be morally compelled by wisdom, to be bound by the consideration of good, is to be free; it is not compulsion in the metaphysical sense.  And metaphysical necessity alone, as I have observed so many times, is opposed to freedom.

238.  I shall not examine the syllogisms that M. Bayle urges in objection in the following chapter (Ch. 152), against the system of the Supralapsarians, and particularly against the oration made by Theodore de Beze at the [274] Conference of Montbeliard in the year 1586.  This conference also only served to increase the acrimony of the parties.  ’God created the World to his glory:  his glory is not known (according to Beze), if his mercy and his justice are not declared; for this cause simply by his grace he decreed for some men life eternal, and for others by a just judgement eternal damnation.  Mercy presupposes misery, justice presupposes guilt.’ (He might have added that misery also supposes guilt.) ’Nevertheless God being good, indeed goodness itself, he created man good and righteous, but unstable, and capable of sinning of his own free will.  Man did not fall at random or rashly, or through causes ordained by some other God, as the Manichaeans hold, but by the providence of God; in such a way notwithstanding, that God was not involved in the fault, inasmuch as man was not constrained to sin.’

239.  This system is not of the best conceived:  it is not well fitted to show forth the wisdom, the goodness and the justice of God; and happily it is almost abandoned to-day.  If there were not other more profound reasons capable of inducing God to permit guilt, the source of misery, there would be neither guilt nor misery in the world, for the reasons alleged here do not suffice.  He would declare his mercy better in preventing misery, and he would declare his justice better in preventing guilt, in advancing virtue, in recompensing it.  Besides, one does not see how he who not only causes a man to be capable of falling, but who so disposes circumstances that they contribute towards causing his fall, is not culpable, if there are no other reasons compelling him thereto.  But when one considers that God, altogether good and wise, must have produced all the virtue, goodness, happiness whereof the best plan of the universe is capable, and that often an evil in some parts may serve the greater good of the whole, one readily concludes that God may have given room for unhappiness, and even permitted guilt, as he has done, without deserving to be blamed.  It is the only remedy that supplies what all systems lack, however they arrange the decrees.  These thoughts have already been favoured by St. Augustine, and one may say of Eve what the poet said of the hand of Mucius Scaevola: 

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
Theodicy from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.