A History of Freedom of Thought eBook

J.B. Bury
This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 187 pages of information about A History of Freedom of Thought.

A History of Freedom of Thought eBook

J.B. Bury
This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 187 pages of information about A History of Freedom of Thought.

[4] The advertisement tax was abolished in 1853, the stamp tax in 1855, the paper duty in 1861, and the optional duty in 1870.

[5] In Austria-Hungary the police have the power to suppress printed matter provisionally.  In Russia the Press was declared free in 1905 by an Imperial decree, which, however, has become a dead letter.  The newspapers are completely under the control of the police.

[6] I have taken these points, illustrating the Monistic attitude to the Churches, from Ostwald’s Monistic Sunday Sermons (German), 1911, 1912.

[7] I may note here that, as this is not a history of thought, I make no reference to recent philosophical speculations (in America, England, and France) which are sometimes claimed as tending to bolster up theology.  But they are all profoundly unorthodox.

[233]

CHAPTER VIII

THE JUSTIFICATION OF LIBERTY OF THOUGHT

Most men who have been brought up in the free atmosphere of a modern State sympathize with liberty in its long struggle with authority and may find it difficult to see that anything can be said for the tyrannical, and as they think extraordinarily perverse, policy by which communities and governments persistently sought to stifle new ideas and suppress free speculation.  The conflict sketched in these pages appears as a war between light and darkness.  We exclaim that altar and throne formed a sinister conspiracy against the progress of humanity.  We look back with horror at the things which so many champions of reason endured at the hands of blind, if not malignant, bearers of authority.

But a more or less plausible case can be made out for coercion.  Let us take the most limited view of the lawful powers of society over its individual members.  Let us lay down, with Mill, that “the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually and collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their members is self-protection,” and that coercion is only justified

[234] for the prevention of harm to others.  This is the minimum claim the State can make, and it will be admitted that it is not only the right but the duty of the State to prevent harm to its members.  That is what it is for.  Now no abstract or independent principle is discoverable, why liberty of speech should be a privileged form of liberty of action, or why society should lay down its arms of defence and fold its hands, when it is persuaded that harm is threatened to it through the speech of any of its members.  The Government has to judge of the danger, and its judgment may be wrong; but if it is convinced that harm is being done, is it not its plain duty to interfere?

This argument supplies an apology for the suppression of free opinion by Governments in ancient and modern times.  It can be urged for the Inquisition, for Censorship of the Press, for Blasphemy laws, for all coercive measures of the kind, that, if excessive or ill-judged, they were intended to protect society against what their authors sincerely believed to be grave injury, and were simple acts of duty. (This apology, of course, does not extend to acts done for the sake of the alleged good of the victims themselves, namely, to secure their future salvation.)

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
A History of Freedom of Thought from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.